I just got "ML for the working programmer" in the mail a few days ago,
and worked through it at a breakneck pace since receiving it. It
turns out that a lot of the stuff from the "Total Functional
Programming" book is also in this one. Paulson goes through the use
of structural recursion and extends the results by showing techniques
for proving a large class of programs to be terminating. Work with
co-algebras and bi-simulation didn't quite make it in, except for a
brief mention about co-variant types leading to the possibility of a
type: D := D → D which is the type of programs in the untyped lambda
calculus, and hence liable to lead one into trouble.
I have to say that having finished the book, this is the single most
interesting programming book that I've read since "Paradigms of
Artificial Intelligence Programming" and "Structure and Interpretation
of Computer Programs". In fact, I would rate this one above the other
two, though I think it might be because of my current interests.
The conjunction of "Total Functional Programming" and "ML for the
Working Programmer" have completely changed my world view of automated
deduction. Interestingly, my advisers work looks even more appealing
from this perspective.
The basic crux of the issue is this. Given that we restrict ourselves
to total functional programming, as described in the aforementioned
article, we will have the ability to prove theorems directly by
manipulation of the program source.
My adviser told me about this the first time that I met him. It at
first seemed like a curiosity. It has however, blossomed into a
completely different way of thinking about how proofs should be
performed.
I've spent the last few days converting proofs into program source,
which I then manipulate equationally. I have a few examples of
inductive proofs that can be written quite naturally as structurally
recursive functions.
Both of these functions are direct "extractions" of a program from a
proofs that I wrote. The second one is a proof with two existential
variables. The two existential variables present themselves as return
values. In the case of "lt" it simply computes a truth value.
The datatype nat = Z | S of nat defines natural numbers with the
correspondence Z=0, S(Z)=1, S(S(Z))=2 etc...
The proof is a proposition that goes like this:
∀n,d:nat. d>0 ∃q,r:nat. n=dq+r ∧ 0≤r<d
You might notice I dropped the restriction on d in the actual source
code. That can be encoded with an auxiliary function in any case.
The proof proceeds inductively, basically you can turn the divide
function inside out to recover the inductive proof.
The base case is n=0 which gives 0=dq+r which gives r=0 and q=0 (since
d is greater than 0). The first case is exemplified in the case
structure above. (Z,Z) = (q,r) the two existential variables are
returned with a valid result for n=0.
The inductive case is this.
n: ∃q,r. n=dq+r ∧ 0≤r<d
(n+1): ∃q',r'. n+1=dq'+r' ∧ 0≤r'<d
if(r+1)<d
then n+1=dq+r+1
We see that this gives us that r'=r+1, q'=q giving us a solution to r' and q' from r and q (and hence solving the n case, gives us some information about n+1)
else n+1 = d(q+1)+r'
which we can rewrite as: n+1 = d(q+1)+r' = dq+d+r'=dq+r+1 so d+r'=r+1,
but r+1 must be at least d otherwise we wouldn't have failed the test
r+1<d, and r' can be no less than zero, so we must choose r'=0
this results in (finally!)
n+1 = d(q+1) with r'=0,q'=q+1
We have a proof! For the extracted program you can look at the source
and see that in fact it mirrors the proof directly, short of a few
simplifications done by hand. Making use of the r,q in the proof of
r' and q' is the same as my use of r and q in my proof of the n+1 case.
I'm looking forward to a deeper understanding of the correspondences
between proofs and programs with my new found capacity to produce actual functional program proofs by extraction manually. I'm also
curious to try my hand at generating termination proofs directly, and
also at making a syntax that more directly supports total functional
programming.
and worked through it at a breakneck pace since receiving it. It
turns out that a lot of the stuff from the "Total Functional
Programming" book is also in this one. Paulson goes through the use
of structural recursion and extends the results by showing techniques
for proving a large class of programs to be terminating. Work with
co-algebras and bi-simulation didn't quite make it in, except for a
brief mention about co-variant types leading to the possibility of a
type: D := D → D which is the type of programs in the untyped lambda
calculus, and hence liable to lead one into trouble.
I have to say that having finished the book, this is the single most
interesting programming book that I've read since "Paradigms of
Artificial Intelligence Programming" and "Structure and Interpretation
of Computer Programs". In fact, I would rate this one above the other
two, though I think it might be because of my current interests.
The conjunction of "Total Functional Programming" and "ML for the
Working Programmer" have completely changed my world view of automated
deduction. Interestingly, my advisers work looks even more appealing
from this perspective.
The basic crux of the issue is this. Given that we restrict ourselves
to total functional programming, as described in the aforementioned
article, we will have the ability to prove theorems directly by
manipulation of the program source.
My adviser told me about this the first time that I met him. It at
first seemed like a curiosity. It has however, blossomed into a
completely different way of thinking about how proofs should be
performed.
I've spent the last few days converting proofs into program source,
which I then manipulate equationally. I have a few examples of
inductive proofs that can be written quite naturally as structurally
recursive functions.
datatype nat = Z | S of nat fun lt n m = case m of Z => false | (S m') => case n of Z => true | (S n') => lt n' m' fun divide n d = case n of Z => (Z,Z) | (S n') => let val (q',r') = divide n' d in case lt (S r') d of true => (q',S r') | false => (S q',Z) end
Both of these functions are direct "extractions" of a program from a
proofs that I wrote. The second one is a proof with two existential
variables. The two existential variables present themselves as return
values. In the case of "lt" it simply computes a truth value.
The datatype nat = Z | S of nat defines natural numbers with the
correspondence Z=0, S(Z)=1, S(S(Z))=2 etc...
The proof is a proposition that goes like this:
∀n,d:nat. d>0 ∃q,r:nat. n=dq+r ∧ 0≤r<d
You might notice I dropped the restriction on d in the actual source
code. That can be encoded with an auxiliary function in any case.
The proof proceeds inductively, basically you can turn the divide
function inside out to recover the inductive proof.
The base case is n=0 which gives 0=dq+r which gives r=0 and q=0 (since
d is greater than 0). The first case is exemplified in the case
structure above. (Z,Z) = (q,r) the two existential variables are
returned with a valid result for n=0.
The inductive case is this.
n: ∃q,r. n=dq+r ∧ 0≤r<d
(n+1): ∃q',r'. n+1=dq'+r' ∧ 0≤r'<d
if(r+1)<d
then n+1=dq+r+1
We see that this gives us that r'=r+1, q'=q giving us a solution to r' and q' from r and q (and hence solving the n case, gives us some information about n+1)
else n+1 = d(q+1)+r'
which we can rewrite as: n+1 = d(q+1)+r' = dq+d+r'=dq+r+1 so d+r'=r+1,
but r+1 must be at least d otherwise we wouldn't have failed the test
r+1<d, and r' can be no less than zero, so we must choose r'=0
this results in (finally!)
n+1 = d(q+1) with r'=0,q'=q+1
We have a proof! For the extracted program you can look at the source
and see that in fact it mirrors the proof directly, short of a few
simplifications done by hand. Making use of the r,q in the proof of
r' and q' is the same as my use of r and q in my proof of the n+1 case.
I'm looking forward to a deeper understanding of the correspondences
between proofs and programs with my new found capacity to produce actual functional program proofs by extraction manually. I'm also
curious to try my hand at generating termination proofs directly, and
also at making a syntax that more directly supports total functional
programming.
Comments
Post a Comment